Kia ora: Have included later on this page an excerpt from Paul Kurtz’s article in Free Inquiry June/July 2006, Why I am a Skeptic about Religious Claims. Paul Kurtz turned 80 on 21 December 2005.

August monthly meeting:Monday 28 August, 7.30 pm until 9 pm, Turnbull House, Wellington. All welcome. Topic:. Kent Stevens will lead a discussion around the issues of the recent conflict in the Middle East. Advance notice: at the September meeting member Jason Curry will lead a discussion around why not to believe in God. At the meeting we do enjoy reading the e-mails with your thoughts, it is good to be in touch, where distance or other commitments make it difficult to attend. e-mail Kent at KentStevens77(at)yahoo.com.

AGM & Seminar: We are beginning to plan for the 2006 AGM and seminar, which will be held in October. Arrangements for speakers are being finalised. A proposed speaker is Dr. Michael Berridge from the Malaghan Institute of Medical Research who will speak on stem cell research. Further details will be advised. If you wish to have information before the newsletter arrives please phone Gaylene at 04 232 4497.

2006 Skeptics Conference: Friday 29 September – Sunday 1 October Kings College Auckland. For more details see www.skeptics.org.nz

Sea of Faith Conference: for details see www.sof.org.nz. Held same weekend as Skeptics but in the Wairarapa.

Radio Access: 11 am 783 kHz August 27. No details. Listen in for a surprise. For those living outside the Wellington reception area it is possible to listen to the broadcast on the internet site: www.accessradio.org.nz. Click on Wellington Access Radio. At the home page click on the talk/link icon. On the Menu on the left hand side of the screen click on Radio, and with your sound up the radio is very audible. You do not require broadband to listen.

Email discussion group: Is operating on Yahoo at http://groups.yahoo.com/group/nzhumanism .

Email News: Those people who have provided an email address receive additional email Humanist News bulletins and items of interest. If you would like to be on the mailing list, please email iain-middleton(at)clear.net.nz . Remember to let us know if you change your email or postal address.

Interested in meeting Humanists travelling in New Zealand? If you would like to meet overseas Humanists travelling in NZ, please e-mail Iain at iain-middleton(at)clear.net.nz or write to PO Box 3372 Wellington. We occasionally receive enquires from overseas Humanists travelling in New Zealand who would like to meet with fellow Humanists.

Two interesting articles below:
First Paul Kurtz at eighty, and
Second an article by Stan Cohen, Don’t look Back

Gaylene Middleton

Why I am a Skeptic about Religions Claims

Why do skeptics doubt the existence of God?

  • The claim that our ultimate moral values are derived from God is highly suspect. The so-called sacred moral codes reflect the socio-historical cultures out of which they emerged. For example, the Old Testament commands that adulterers, blasphemers, disobedient sons, bastards, witches, and homosexuals be stoned to death. It threatens collective guilt: punishment is inflicted by Jehovah on the children’s children of unbelievers. It defends patriarchy and the dominion of men over women. It condones slavery and genocide in the name of God.
  • The New Testament consigns “unto Caesar the things that are Caesar’s”; it demands that women be obedient to their husbands; it accepts faith healing, exorcisms, and miracles; it exalts obedience over independence, fear and trembling over courage, and piety over sell-determination.
  • The Qur’an does not tolerate dissent, freedom of conscience, or the right to unbelief. It denies the rights of women. It exhorts jihad, holy war against infidels. It demands utter submission to the Word of God as revealed by Muhammad. It rejects the separation of mosque and state, thus installing the law of sharia and the theocracy of imams and mullahs.
  • From the fatherhood of God, contradictory moral commandments have been derived; theists have often lined up on opposite sides of moral issues. Believers have stood for and against war; for and against slavery; for and against capital punishment, some embracing retribution, others mercy and rehabilitation; for and against the divine right of kings, slavery, and patriarchy; for and against the emancipation of women; for and against the absolute prohibition of contraception, euthanasia, and abortion; for and against sexual and gender equality; for and against freedom of scientific research; for and against the libertarian ideals of a free society.
  • True believers have in the past often found little room for human autonomy individual freedom, or sell-reliance. They have emphasized submission to the word of God instead of sell-determination, faith over reason, credulity over doubt. All too often they have had little confidence in the ability of humans to solve problems and create a better future by drawing on their own resources. In the face of tragedy they supplicate to God through prayer instead of summoning the courage to overcome adversity and build a better future. The skeptic concludes, “No deity will save us; if we are to be saved it must be by our own efforts.”
  • The traditional religions have too often waged wars of intolerance not only against other religions or ideologies that dispute the legitimacy of their divine revelations but even against sects that are mere variants of the same religion (e.g., Catholic versus Protestant, Shiite versus Sunni). Religions claim to speak in the name of God, yet bloodshed, tyranny and untold horrors have often been justified on behalf of holy creeds. True believers have all too often opposed human progress: the abolition of slavery, the liberation of women, the extension of equal rights to transgendered people and gays, the expansion of democracy and human rights.

I realize that liberal religionists generally have rejected the absolutist creeds of fundamentalism. Fortunately they have been influenced by modern democratic and humanistic values, which mitigate fundamentalism’s inherent intolerance. Nevertheless, even many liberal believers embrace a key article of faith in the three major Abrahamic religions, Christianity Islam, and Judaism: the promise of eternal salvation.

Paul Kurtz

Extracted from an article in Free Inquiry June/July 2006 Vol. 26 No. 4 www.secularhumanism.org
The full text of this article is available at:

http://www.secularhumanism.org/


REPARATIONS
D o n ‘ t l o o k b a c k

Is obsession with wrongs of the past threatening our commitment to the future, asks STAN COHEN

There was once a political sense in which to be conservative meant to be backward-looking, to be ‘living in’ or ‘dwelling on’ the past. Progressives and radicals were, as the names imply, supposed to be more ‘forward-looking’. Somehow, in the terrain of post-Holocaust political morality, these attributions became reversed.

The emergence of international human rights rhetoric, the dramatic ‘transition’ in many countries from varieties of authoritarian regime to democracy, revelations about past cover-ups and unacknowledged historical crimes: all this has shifted the progressive gaze backwards into the past. Historical injustices had to be exposed, the guilty punished, victims compensated, damage repaired, evil exorcised, remorse expressed.

The natural response of the conservative establishment, by contrast, was denial and avoidance: draw the line on the past, close the book, don’t open old wounds, let bygones be bygones. Suddenly the radicals are trapped in the past while the conservatives are all about tomorrow.

Such general attributions of political positions and reversals are obviously of limited application to specific cases. But certainly the ‘justice in transition’ discourse which dominated the progressive agenda since the 1980s embodies just this kind of backwards shift in emphasis.

There were major differences between and within the three major blocks of collapsing regimes – the Latin American juntas, state communism and (sui generis) apartheid South Africa. But all these transitions were built on the promise that a thorough expurgation of the past was necessary for a stable democratic future.

Thus the obsessive search after ‘what really happened’ (Truth); tracking down the perpetrators and their masters to be punished in the name of retribution or deterrence (Justice); compensating victims and survivors for their past losses; and extracting apologies, remorse and contrition from the wrongdoers. Even the forward-looking quest for reconciliation is unthinkable without information about the past: I must know just what these people did before I can be reconciled to living with them now.

Two other deeply resonant forms of reparation politics also, by definition, must look backwards: first, the rituals of apology and forgiveness; second, the sanctification of private memory work and public commemoration. While all this was unfolding in the international news arena (genocides, political massacres, disappearances, torture, trafficking), the more domestic tragedies of everyday life also increasingly became the object of reparation politics

Whether it was adult men alleging sexual abuse by Catholic priests 40 years earlier; indigenous people making claims about land rights violated centuries ago; women whose lives had been wrecked by faulty cancer screening, or survivors of airplane, rail or ship accidents, calls would come for an independent inquiry (‘Truth Commission?’), to be followed by legal action for damages and compensation – democratic but non-political versions of the grand ambition of “making whole what has been smashed”.

This is the title of John Torpey’s just-published critique of recent reparations politics (Making Whole What Has Been Smashed: On Reparations Politics, Harvard University Press). The phrase derives from Walter Benjamin’s description of a Paul Klee painting (Anglus Novus) in which an angel in flight contemplates the wreckage of the past piling up at its feet. “The angel would like to stay, awaken the dead and make whole what has been smashed.” But a storm blowing from Paradise drives him backward into the future. “This storm is what we call progress,” Benjamin laconically writes.

Torpey certainly does not argue that all political projects that look backwards – to redress wrongs, compensate for losses, repair the shattered fragments of a violent past – are futile, diversionary and literally ‘reactionary,’ and should be replaced by the more forward-looking, utopian visions of classic progressive politics, notably socialism. But even his more moderate thesis goes quite far: that for many people who automatically see themselves (and are seen) as progressives or radicals, the past has extensively replaced the future as the temporal horizon in which to think about politics.”

This overstates the general case, certainly outside the United States, but does apply to the many arenas of public life influenced by the legacies of identity politics and the emerging human rights culture of the 1980s and 1990s. If the motto of transitional justice was ‘coming to terms with the past,’ its iconic image was Archbishop Tutu, benignly presiding over the South African Truth and Reconciliation Commission. In another version – more politically disruptive – there is the resonant narrative of reparations for African Americans for the damage done by slavery.

There is obviously a loose sense -in personal as well as political life -where an excessive preoccupation with the past is a block to making any constructive plans about the future. It literally stops you from ‘getting on with things.’ This preoccupation, however, may not always be quite as pathological (“usually a sign that something is amiss”) as Torpey suggests. He is being a little overdramatically historicist to explain this intensive and censorious recovery of the past as “a defensive response to the disorientation induced by the collapse of an invigorating conception of a common destiny.”

Torpey knows anyway that looking backwards is not in itself the problem; he does not appear to dispute Freud’s revolutionary claim that human emancipation depends on coming to terms with an unmastered past. The problem lies in the rather special ways in which routes to the future are traced from nightmares of the past.

Only in South Africa (where traditional religious thinking of both masters and servants was not displaced by the newly imported psychobabble of the professional elites) could one institution – the Truth and Reconciliation Commission -actually have combined the three most problematic such ways: The legalistic (‘tort-like’) model of compensation (in practice, a policy that has been hardly implemented); the therapeutic ideal of truth-telling, with its lexicon of trauma, hidden suffering, repression, ‘closure and belief that ‘revealing is healing’; and the theological tropes of confession, expiation and forgiveness.

The widespread diffusion of these models (in different mixtures) was made possible by yet another unlikely three-part combination: multi-culturalism and identity politics; concern for the needs and rights of victims; and the uncritical adoption of strict legalism by the human rights movement.

The wide range of reparation politics – from purely symbolic claims to acknowledge the suffering of historical victims to detailed financial inventories of damages awarded to current, living claimants – hardly allows much general evaluation. Torpey uses three case studies to show how law-like claims for redress by special victim groups are not easily translated into collective political visions: the redress settlements concerning Japanese-Americans and Japanese-Canadians interned during World War 11; the legal strategy for claiming reparations for slavery for black Americans; and the current forms of reparation politics in post Truth Commission South Africa. Other cases – the Japanese comfort women, the Australian displacement of aboriginal people – tell the same story.

Torpey is rightly suspicious about the growing ranks of entrepreneurs of memory’ – theologians who see history in redemptory terms, therapists searching for past traumas and every hack intellectual who sees history as a repository of ‘lessons’ for the present. The most serious danger to visionary politics comes from seeing the history of human oppression as a series of potentially justiciable civil offences. We need to listen more cautiously to the legalistic tone of so much current activism, debate and political action – what German philosopher Jurgun Habermas describes as the “juridiflcation of politics”.

Marina Warner, in an essay on the politics of apology for openDemocracy.net, is surely right, though, that the critique of reparations politics ignores the intrinsic value of political struggles for regret, apology and remorse. Apology, as she says, “adds to the sum of justice in the world.” She also reminds us of the ideological atrocities of the century that were committed not to repair the past, but in the name of some political blueprint of the future.

One reading of ‘The End of History’ is that these dominantly Left-wing ideologues and theorists of revolutionary slaughter – the Stains and the Pol Pots – may never be seen again. But in place of them the mass victims of the future may be the slow but steady sacrifices required by a less visible ideology: the bland utopia of the free market. And who will apologise to them?

Stan Cohen is Emeritus Professor of Sociology at LSE